Subjectivity is no barrier Citation
نویسنده
چکیده
Palmer’s “subjectivity barrier” seems to be erected on a popular but highly suspect conception of visual experience, and his “color room” argument is invalid. Palmer beautifully articulates a view that many philosophers and psychologists have found compelling: In attempting to understand the mind, scientists face an impenetrable “subjectivity barrier,” behind which lies the “nature of [our] experiences themselves” (sect. 2.1, para. 2 and 3).1 And although Palmer sometimes sweetens the pill with such locutions as “scientists would never know with certainty” (sect. 2.1, para. 1), and “it may not be possible to be sure” (sect. 2.2, para. 3), it is perfectly clear that the conclusions of his arguments are – setting futuristic brainometers aside – that we (not just “behavioral scientists”) have absolutely no reason to believe (not just no “objective knowledge”) that others have experiences with the same “intrinsic qualities” as our own, or even that they have any experiences at all (sect. 2.5, para. 8). Thus, what might seem at first glance a sober essay curbing the pretensions of science to explain consciousness is in fact a radically skeptical manifesto. According to Palmer, we can at best know about the relational structure of others’ experiences – the similarities and differences they bear to each other. (For brevity’s sake I shall ignore his further claim that we cannot know that others have experiences.) Skepticism follows because Palmer holds that fixing this relational structure does not fix the “sensory qualities” of experiences. Palmer’s main examples of a difference in sensory quality with no difference in relational structure are variants of the usual “spectrum inversion” case (Shoemaker 1981). No doubt some commentators will attack Palmer’s argument by questioning whether our color space is as symmetric as Palmer makes it out to be. But this response does not dig deep enough, because on Palmer’s conception there may well be sensory qualities “alien” to us that could occupy the relational structure of our experiences. A potentially more promising response disputes Palmer’s crucial claim that sensory qualities can vary independently of relational structure. This response subdivides into two: the first agrees with Palmer that interpersonal comparisons of sensory qualities make sense (Clark 1993; Hilbert & Kalderon, in press), whereas the second denies that they do (Stalnaker, in press).2 As I am unconvinced that the response just mentioned can be made to work, I shall try a different tack, and present a natural conception of visual experience on which it is hard to get Palmer’s skeptical worries going.3 Imagine seeing a red object – the proverbial ripe tomato. Focus your attention on the salient property of the tomato that it shares with cherries and strawberries. That property is redness, right? And of course red objects – like tomatoes and cherries – look more similar, with respect to color, to orange objects than they do to green objects. These similarity relations among colored objects induce corresponding similarity relations among our experiences of color, rather than the other way around. It is not true that red objects are more similar to orange objects than they are to green objects because our experiences of red objects are more similar to our experiences of orange objects than they are to our experiences of green objects. Rather, the explanation goes the other way: Our experiences are similar because the objects of the experiences are similar. This is because when people have visual experiences they are only aware of what visually appears to them, or of what their experience represents: as it might be, the presence of a red tomato. They are not aware (at least, not without further effort) of their experiences. And similarly with the “nature of the experiences themselves”: The perceived nature of the objects of perception (e.g., the redness of the tomato) explains the nature of perceptions of objects. If a person has a visual experience that represents the tomato as being red, then nothing else needs to be added to this experience for it to have the distinctive “sensory quality of redness” (sect. 2.1, para. 3) that Palmer thinks is hidden from scientific enquiry. Therefore, because there appears to be no special problem about knowing whether objects visually appear red to people, there is no special problem about knowing the nature of others’ visual experiences, and thus there is no “subjectivity barrier.” Palmer may have been seduced by the following perennially appealing argument for thinking that something else needs to be added to a visual experience that represents something as red for it to have the “sensory quality of redness.” Imagine having a “red” afterimage. Perhaps unreflectively you would be inclined to call the distinctive property of the image “red,” but surely the image cannot really be red – red is a property of physical objects like tomatoes, not “mental objects” like images. So call the property of the image “R” instead. But obviously R is present when you see objects, like ripe tomatoes. And because “mental objects” like images can have R, it does not seem likely that R can ever be a property of a physical object like a tomato. So when you see that a tomato is red, you are aware that the tomato is red and that some image-like thing has R. It is the presence of an R-image that gives your experiences of red objects (and certain afterimages) their distinctive “sensory quality”; similarly, the distinctive sensory quality of your experiences of green objects is due to the presence of a Gimage. And now, of course, the question naturally arises whether others’ experiences of red objects are in fact attended by G-images rather than R-images. As tempting as this reasoning is, it is wrong. If R is to explain the sensory quality of your experience of a ripe tomato, then it is not sufficient that the experience involve an image that has R: It must visually appear to you that the image has R (imagine that even though the image has R, it appears to have G; in that case you would have an experience with the sensory quality distinctive of your experiences of green objects). But now the alleged fact that the image has R is doing no explanatory work: The sensory quality of your experience is solely explained by the fact that it appears to you that the image has R, irrespective of whether the image has R. So the introduction of R was an idle wheel – redness would do the job just as well. Your afterimage experience was a kind of hallucination: It visually appeared to you that something was red (that is what gave your experience its distinctive sensory quality), but nothing in the scene before your eyes was red (that is why it was a kind of hallucination). Furthermore, although it seemed to you that there was an image floating before your eyes, in fact there was no object – not even a mental one – there at all. Finally, as has been pointed out numerous times (e.g., CopeCommentary/Palmer: Color and consciousness BEHAVIORAL AND BRAIN SCIENCES (1999) 22:6 949 land 1993), the Chinese room argument is fallacious. The conclusion concerns the system (it cannot understand Chinese), but the premise concerns a part of the system (the man does not understand Chinese). The argument is an instance of “x is not F, x is part of y, therefore y is not F,” and so is invalid.4 Thus Palmer’s “color room” argument fails to show anything whatever about functionalism and experience.
منابع مشابه
A Critical Study of the Theory of the Subjectivity of Moral Values With Reference to Mackay's Theory
According to mackay, values in general and ethical values in particular are subjective in nature. That is, they have no foundation independent of mans wishes and subjective human inelinations. According to his definition of subjectivism, values have no foundation, but the basis of values are not independent of manchr('39')s desires. He offers two arguments for his theory. One is based on the r...
متن کاملCitation Statistics
This is a report about the use and misuse of citation data in the assessment of scientific research. The idea that research assessment must be done using “simple and objective” methods is increasingly prevalent today. The “simple and objective” methods are broadly interpreted as bibliometrics, that is, citation data and the statistics derived from them. There is a belief that citation statistic...
متن کاملSurrealistic Subjectivity and lingual in Tamhidat e Eynolghozat
This article has no abstract.
متن کاملMHSubLex: Using Metaheuristic Methods for Subjectivity Classification of Microblogs
In Web 2.0, people are free to share their experiences, views, and opinions. One of the problems that arises in web 2.0 is the sentiment analysis of texts produced by users in outlets such as Twitter. One of main the tasks of sentiment analysis is subjectivity classification. Our aim is to classify the subjectivity of Tweets. To this end, we create subjectivity lexicons in which the words into ...
متن کاملThe Psychological Element in the Phenomenological Analysis of Human Subjectivity
The aim of this paper is to depict the psychological element in phenomenological analysis of the human subjectivity. This analysis should be considered within the philosophical context provided by philosophers of 18th and 19th centuries, and very specifically by Kant as his transcendental philosophy was a turning point for later debates on the human subjectivity. In this paper, I will consider ...
متن کاملQuantitative Safety and Health Assessment Based on Fuzzy Inference and AHP at Preliminary Design Stage
Quantitative assessment is the most important means to identify hazard potential and manage risk for an industrial process. The implement of quantitative assessment in the early stage will help to develop inherently safer process, eliminating the hazard and reduce the possibility of accidental chain events and the magnitude of consequences. In this paper, after reviewing the presently available...
متن کاملذخیره در منابع من
با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید
عنوان ژورنال:
دوره شماره
صفحات -
تاریخ انتشار 2000